Quick Facts
Born:
April 19, 1883, Lemberg, Austria-Hungary [now Lviv, Ukraine]
Died:
July 14, 1953, Boston, Massachusetts, U.S. (aged 70)

Richard von Mises (born April 19, 1883, Lemberg, Austria-Hungary [now Lviv, Ukraine]—died July 14, 1953, Boston, Massachusetts, U.S.) was an Austrian-born American mathematician, engineer, and positivist philosopher who notably advanced statistics and probability theory.

Von Mises’s early work centred on geometry and mechanics, especially the theory of turbines. In 1913, during his appointment at the University of Strassburg (1909–18; now the French University of Strasbourg), he gave the first German university course on aviation, and he contributed to the theory of airfoil design. In 1915–16 he constructed a 600-horsepower airplane for the Austrian army on which he served as a test pilot.

Von Mises had to leave Strasbourg after the German defeat in World War I. In 1920 he became director of the Institute for Applied Mathematics at the University of Berlin. Although a Roman Catholic by faith, von Mises was classified as Jewish by the Nazi government, and so he fled Germany in 1933 and accepted a position with the University of Istanbul. In 1939 he joined the staff of Harvard University, where he contributed notably to the study of elasticity and cofounded the series Advances in Applied Mechanics.

Equations written on blackboard
Britannica Quiz
Numbers and Mathematics

In 1919 von Mises developed his famous and controversial frequency approach to probability. In this regard, he developed the axiom of convergence, which holds that the relative frequency of an event converges on a limit as longer and longer sequences are drawn from some “reference class,” and the axiom of randomness, which holds that the limit for a relative frequency is independent of any particular randomly chosen infinite subsequence. He published his probabilistic work (with his positivistic interpretations) in Probability, Statistics and Truth (1928). This effort to formulate an objective definition met with certain philosophical objections. Nevertheless, the frequency approach, minus its dependence on infinite reference classes, was rehabilitated in the 1960s and continues to gain proponents. In 1939 von Mises introduced the famous “birthday problem,” which asked how many people must be gathered before the probability of two people sharing a birthday exceeds 50 percent. (The surprising answer: 23.)

Von Mises’s Positivism: A Study in Human Understanding (1951) summarizes his views on science and life. He was also a leading authority on the Austrian poet Rainer Maria Rilke.

This article was most recently revised and updated by Encyclopaedia Britannica.

probability and statistics, the branches of mathematics concerned with the laws governing random events, including the collection, analysis, interpretation, and display of numerical data. Probability has its origin in the study of gambling and insurance in the 17th century, and it is now an indispensable tool of both social and natural sciences. Statistics may be said to have its origin in census counts taken thousands of years ago; as a distinct scientific discipline, however, it was developed in the early 19th century as the study of populations, economies, and moral actions and later in that century as the mathematical tool for analyzing such numbers. For technical information on these subjects, see probability theory and statistics. See also conditional probability, probability density function, likelihood, and geometric distribution.

Early probability

Games of chance

The modern mathematics of chance is usually dated to a correspondence between the French mathematicians Pierre de Fermat and Blaise Pascal in 1654. Their inspiration came from a problem about games of chance, proposed by a remarkably philosophical gambler, the chevalier de Méré. De Méré inquired about the proper division of the stakes when a game of chance is interrupted. Suppose two players, A and B, are playing a three-point game, each having wagered 32 pistoles, and are interrupted after A has two points and B has one. How much should each receive?

Fermat and Pascal proposed somewhat different solutions, though they agreed about the numerical answer. Each undertook to define a set of equal or symmetrical cases, then to answer the problem by comparing the number for A with that for B. Fermat, however, gave his answer in terms of the chances, or probabilities. He reasoned that two more games would suffice in any case to determine a victory. There are four possible outcomes, each equally likely in a fair game of chance. A might win twice, AA; or first A then B might win; or B then A; or BB. Of these four sequences, only the last would result in a victory for B. Thus, the odds for A are 3:1, implying a distribution of 48 pistoles for A and 16 pistoles for B.

Pascal thought Fermat’s solution unwieldy, and he proposed to solve the problem not in terms of chances but in terms of the quantity now called “expectation.” Suppose B had already won the next round. In that case, the positions of A and B would be equal, each having won two games, and each would be entitled to 32 pistoles. A should receive his portion in any case. B’s 32, by contrast, depend on the assumption that he had won the first round. This first round can now be treated as a fair game for this stake of 32 pistoles, so that each player has an expectation of 16. Hence A’s lot is 32 + 16, or 48, and B’s is just 16.

Games of chance such as this one provided model problems for the theory of chances during its early period, and indeed they remain staples of the textbooks. A posthumous work of 1665 by Pascal on the “arithmetic triangle” now linked to his name (see binomial theorem) showed how to calculate numbers of combinations and how to group them to solve elementary gambling problems. Fermat and Pascal were not the first to give mathematical solutions to problems such as these. More than a century earlier, the Italian mathematician, physician, and gambler Girolamo Cardano calculated odds for games of luck by counting up equally probable cases. His little book, however, was not published until 1663, by which time the elements of the theory of chances were already well known to mathematicians in Europe. It will never be known what would have happened had Cardano published in the 1520s. It cannot be assumed that probability theory would have taken off in the 16th century. When it began to flourish, it did so in the context of the “new science” of the 17th-century scientific revolution, when the use of calculation to solve tricky problems had gained a new credibility. Cardano, moreover, had no great faith in his own calculations of gambling odds, since he believed also in luck, particularly in his own. In the Renaissance world of monstrosities, marvels, and similitudes, chance—allied to fate—was not readily naturalized, and sober calculation had its limits.

Italian-born physicist Dr. Enrico Fermi draws a diagram at a blackboard with mathematical equations. circa 1950.
Britannica Quiz
Define It: Math Terms