ad hominem, type of argument or attack that appeals to prejudice or feelings or irrelevantly impugns another person’s character instead of addressing the facts or claims made by the latter.
Ad hominem arguments are often taught to be a type of fallacy, an erroneous form of argumentation, although this is not necessarily the case. A number of scholars have noted that questioning a person’s character is a fallacy only insofar as the person’s character is not logically relevant to the debate. Indeed, philosophy textbooks often list ad hominem arguments as a type of informal fallacy but add the important proviso that the person must be attacked “irrelevantly.” For example, a scientist may reject a colleague’s argument because of the latter’s taste in music or hairstyle. These idiosyncratic and subjective traits are in no way related to the truthfulness of the colleague’s argument, and attacking the person rather than the substance of their argument would be a clear instance of the ad hominem fallacy. However, courts do commonly take into account the character of a witness, and questioning the statements of a chronic liar would not be fallacious since it logically relates to the possibility of their speech being itself a lie.
Scholars generally recognize five subcategories of ad hominem arguments:
The idea that ad hominem arguments can be legitimately raised in the case of testimonies is generally recognized. Some scholars argue that ad hominem arguments can also be legitimate when they challenge someone’s argument as being self-interested or driven by a dogmatic bias (such as in the bias and “poisoning the well” types), but this view is contested since it relies on a subjective assessment of inner motives. For instance, an environmentalist might argue in favour of reducing the use of carbon-emitting energy sources. Insofar as the environmentalist is grounding their position in facts and logic, it would be fallacious to dismiss such an argument on the sole basis of the person’s deep preexisting commitment to environmental protection. In some respect, scholarly debates about the possibility of non-fallacious use of ad hominem arguments revolve around the tension between formal logic, which is primarily concerned with the validity of statements, and rhetoric, which is primarily concerned with persuasion. Since Aristotle, scholars of rhetoric have been interested not only in the logical and substantive soundness of an argument (its logos) but also in the passions raised by the speech or text (the pathos) as well as the character of the person making the argument (their ethos).
The use of ad hominem attacks is a common feature of modern politics, particularly in campaign advertising. One reason for the popularity of ad hominem arguments in politics is simply their effectiveness. Ad hominem accusations are easy to deploy against a political opponent. They can persuade an audience to dismiss an argument without the need to respond to its underlying facts or reasoning and can diminish the opponent’s credibility, making it difficult for the person being attacked to effectively reply. Furthermore, an ad hominem attack can have a long-lasting impact since it can tarnish the overall reputation of the opponent rather than their campaign ideas.