modal logic

verifiedCite
While every effort has been made to follow citation style rules, there may be some discrepancies. Please refer to the appropriate style manual or other sources if you have any questions.
Select Citation Style
Share
Share to social media
URL
https://www.britannica.com/topic/modal-logic
Feedback
Corrections? Updates? Omissions? Let us know if you have suggestions to improve this article (requires login).
Thank you for your feedback

Our editors will review what you’ve submitted and determine whether to revise the article.

Also known as: alethic modal logic

modal logic, formal systems incorporating modalities such as necessity, possibility, impossibility, contingency, strict implication, and certain other closely related concepts.

The most straightforward way of constructing a modal logic is to add to some standard nonmodal logical system a new primitive operator intended to represent one of the modalities, to define other modal operators in terms of it, and to add axioms or transformation rules involving those modal operators. For example, one may add the symbol L, which means “It is necessary that,” to the classical propositional calculus; thus, Lp is read as “It is necessary that p.” The possibility operator M (“It is possible that”) may be defined in terms of L as Mp = ¬L¬p (where ¬ means “not”). In addition to the axioms and rules of inference of classical propositional logic, such a system might have two axioms and one rule of inference of its own. Some characteristic axioms of modal logic are: Lpp and L(pq) ⊃ (LpLq). The new rule of inference in this system is the rule of necessitation: if p is a theorem of the system, then so is Lp. Stronger systems of modal logic can be obtained by adding additional axioms. For example, some add the axiom LpLLp, while others add the axiom MpLMp. See formal logic: modal logic.

This article was most recently revised and updated by Brian Duignan.