problem of other minds
- Related Topics:
- philosophy of mind
problem of other minds, in philosophy, the problem of justifying the commonsensical belief that others besides oneself possess minds and are capable of thinking or feeling somewhat as one does oneself. The problem has been discussed within both the analytic (Anglo-American) and the continental philosophical traditions, and since the 20th century it has provided a matter for dispute in epistemology, logic, and philosophy of mind.
The traditional philosophical justification for belief in other minds is the argument from analogy, which, as cogently stated by John Stuart Mill, a 19th-century empiricist, argues that, because one’s body and outward behaviour are observably similar to the bodies and behaviour of others, one is justified by analogy in believing that others have feelings like one’s own and not simply the bodies and behaviour of automatons.
This argument has been repeatedly attacked since the 1940s, although some philosophers continue to defend certain forms of it. Norman Malcolm, an American disciple of Ludwig Wittgenstein, asserted that the argument is either superfluous or its conclusion unintelligible to the person who would make it, because, in order to know what the conclusion “that human figure has thoughts and feelings” means, one would have to know what criteria are involved in correctly or incorrectly stating that someone has thoughts or feelings—and knowledge of these criteria would render the argument from analogy unnecessary. Defenders of the argument have maintained, however, that, since both the person making the argument and others describe inner feelings in similar ways and seemingly understand each other, reference to a common language justifies the argument from analogy better than does observation of similarities of bodies and outward behaviour.
Another objection to the argument is that it seems to assume that one in fact knows what it is to have feelings simply by introspection. This assumption has been objected to by followers of Wittgenstein, who think that it leads to the possibility of a “private language” to describe one’s own sensations, a possibility that Wittgenstein rejected on various grounds. Such philosophers maintain that one simply does not know what one’s own feelings are in a way appropriate to the argument until one has learned from experience with others how to describe such feelings in appropriate language. Some philosophers have thought, however, that this situation leads to the conclusion that one can be wrong when one says, “My tooth aches” in the same way that one can be mistaken when one says, “John’s tooth aches.” This thesis is unacceptable to many, who hold that sincere first-person present-tense statements about sensations cannot be false—i.e., they are “incorrigible.”
Discussion of such problems tends to lead quickly into difficulties of providing an adequate analysis of statements about one’s own sensations. The approach to the problem of other minds within existentialism is exemplified in a long chapter of L’Être et le néant (1943; Being and Nothingness), by Jean-Paul Sartre.