Cognitive psychology proposes yet another way to study the causal mechanisms of animal behaviour. The aim of cognitive psychology is to explain an animal’s behaviour in terms of its mental organization for information processing (that is, how the animal acquires, stores, and acts on information present in its world). By studying cognitive mechanisms of an animal, one may study how the animal perceives, learns, memorizes, and makes decisions.
Consider, for example, crows (Corvus brachyrhynchos) that crack walnuts open by dropping them from heights of 5 to 10 metres (about 16 to 33 feet) or more onto rocks, roads, or sidewalks. The birds generally avoid dropping the nuts onto soil, where they would be unlikely to break open. Remarkably, the crows can discriminate between black and English walnuts, for they drop the harder black walnuts from greater heights. In addition, when a crow drops a nut, it takes into account the likelihood that a fellow crow might steal the contents before it can be retrieved. If fewer competing crows are perched nearby, the crow carries a nut higher into the air before releasing it. Thus, numerous processes of perception, learning, and decision-making activity underlie the crows’ nut-cracking behaviour.
Each of these processes may be analyzed. For example, how do crows judge the height from which to drop nuts? Do they have to learn to adjust the dropping height in relation to the type of walnut? When faced with the conflicting conditions of having a hard-shelled black walnut and seeing a number of other crows nearby, how do they decide what drop height to use?
Until the 1970s, students of animal cognition eschewed speculation about the unobservable processing of information, limiting themselves to explaining behaviours in terms of quantifiable relationships between stimuli and responses. Today, however, they make use of behaviour as a window into how an animal’s nervous system processes information. Students of cognition also emphasize the investigation of behaviours in which the animal does not simply respond to immediate stimuli but relies on stored representations of objects and events. For some investigators, mental representations of the environment are the essence of cognition. According to this view, known as the computational-representational approach, the experience of an animal results in the formation in the brain of isomorphisms between brain processes and events in the world. The brain then performs computations on these representations that are ultimately converted to behavioral outputs. For example, a bird assessing the availability of berries on a bush might store information about the time at which it finds each berry as it searches the bush. It might then convert this information, through a brain process equivalent to division, into a representation of the rate of berry collection.
It is possible, however, that the computational-representational approach exaggerates the richness and detail of animals’ representations and the complexity of the brain processes operating on them. A good illustration comes from studies of the mechanisms by which ants (Cataglyphis fortis) living in the Sahara desert navigate home after conducting a circuitous search for food (mainly dead insects). Such a search can take these ants 100 metres (about 330 feet) or more (equivalent to 10,000 body lengths) from the entrance of their underground nest. To get back home, the ants rely on landmarks as visual signposts to show the way. Originally, it was assumed that these ants and other insects that orient using landmarks are able to store their knowledge of the nest environs in maplike internal representations called “cognitive maps.” Doing so would give an ant tremendous flexibility in homing: equipped with a bird’s-eye knowledge of the terrain over which it travels, an ant could return even from points where it had never before been. The mental representation used by these ants in landmark guidance is, however, actually somewhat simpler. Experiments have revealed that each ant stores a two-dimensional visual template—a kind of snapshot—of the landmark array it saw when it left its nest. When returning to its nest, the ant moves so as to match the current visual image as closely as possible with the memorized template. The snapshot-matching mechanism, unlike the cognitive-map one, enables an ant to steer its way home only from points it has recently visited, as opposed to novel sites to which it might be displaced by an experimenter. Although this mental mechanism provides a less complete and less flexible solution to the problem of finding home, it is entirely sufficient for the problems that desert ants routinely face.
An unseen and therefore largely unappreciated aspect of behaviour is the use of decision-making rules or “Darwinian algorithms.” Organisms rely on these rules to process information from their physical and social environments and result in particular behavioral outputs that guide key behavioral and life-history decisions. Darwinian algorithms are made up of the sensory and cognitive processes that perceive and prioritize cues within an individual’s perceptual range. These inputs are then translated into motor outputs. A Darwinian algorithm may involve a stimulus threshold (such as “when the day-length exceeds 10 hours, migrate north”) or may depend on the occurrence of a cue that is normally associated with a fitness-enhancing outcome (such as “build nests in dense vegetation where chick survival is predictably high”). Darwinian algorithms are shaped through evolutionary time by the specific selective regime of each population. Which cues are relied upon depends on the certainty with which a cue can be recognized, the reliability of the relationship between the cue and the anticipated environmental outcome, and the fitness benefits of making a correct decision versus the costs of making an incorrect decision. In general, Darwinian algorithms underlying behavioral and life-history decisions are only as complex as is necessary to yield adaptive outcomes under a species’ normal environmental circumstances but not so complex as to cover all experimentally or anthropogenically induced contingencies.
An intriguing question in the study of animal cognition is the role of consciousness. Humans easily distinguish between merely responding to objects and being conscious of them. For example, while driving along a highway deep in thought or conversation, the driver may suddenly realize that he has not been conscious of the road for the past several miles. Indeed, it is well documented that humans can effectively perceive, memorize, process, and even act on objects and events without the kind of awareness that underlies a verbal report of consciousness. It is possible, therefore, that the behaviour of animals occurs without conscious awareness. However, given that humans have consciousness, it seems reasonable to suppose that individuals in other species, especially social species (such as primates), also experience at least a rudimentary form of consciousness. To think otherwise would be to presume an evolutionary discontinuity between humans and all other forms of life. Thus, the possibility that at least some of the behaviour of animals is accompanied by conscious thinking seems reasonable.
Although most students of animal behaviour accept the idea that animal consciousness is a likely possibility, some argue that it is not yet possible to know whether any particular animal experiences consciousness because it is a private, subjective, and, ultimately, unknowable state. In contrast, cognitive ethologists (a separate group of animal behaviourists), most notably American biophysicist and animal behaviourist Donald Griffin, argue that animals are undoubtedly conscious, since individuals from a wide variety of species behave with apparent intentions of achieving certain goals. For example, chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes) stalking a monkey high above them in the treetops will distribute themselves among the trees that would otherwise provide the monkey with an escape route and attack the creature simultaneously. Similarly, groups of female lions (Panthera leo) fan out widely and then coordinate their attacks on ungulate prey. In another example, a raven (Corvus corax), when presented with the novel situation of a meat morsel dangling from a long string tied to a perch, will study the situation briefly before it acts. Subsequently, the raven will quickly procure the meat by repeatedly pulling up a length of the string with its beak and clamping each length pulled up with its feet while sitting on the perch. Studies of the states and mechanisms of animal consciousness represent important frontiers of future research.