Contemporary political discourse
- Related Topics:
- public opinion
- propaganda
- false flag
- disinformation
- public
News •
The second and third of these strands have been most influential in shaping the thinking of Western theorists since the late 20th century. After a period of relative philosophical disinterest in the term in the middle decades of the 20th century, the terminology of civil society became ubiquitous in political thinking during the 1980s. Many of the ideas of this phase of its intellectual history can be connected to the three traditions previously identified.
The English strand has been powerfully reappropriated in the contemporary period by various neoliberal theorists and ideologues. For them, civil society stands as a synonym for the ideal of the free market accompanied by a constitutionally limited, but powerful, state. This last idea figured powerfully in the idealization of civil society that prevailed in eastern European intellectual circles following the fall of the Berlin Wall in 1989. In these settings, civil society signified either the survival (in countries like Czechoslovakia and Poland) of a web of autonomous associations that were independent of the state and that bound citizens together in matters of common concern or a necessary means of achieving the economic prosperity and civil freedoms of Western democracy.
The German strand’s concern with the sources and importance of the ethical ends learned through participation in the corporations of civil society reemerged in the work of a body of American political scientists and theorists who came to view civil society organizations as sources of the stocks of social capital and mutual reciprocity that a successful democracy is supposed to require.
And, third, the Scottish conception was powerfully revived by left-inclined thinkers who hoped to provide a more pluralist, and less statist, reformulation of a socialist ideology that was experiencing a profound political recession among Western publics.
As the Canadian philosopher Charles Taylor observed, these and other influential ways of thinking about civil society rested upon the twin assumptions that, in empirical terms, independent civil societies did come into existence at various points from the 18th through the 20th century and that their existence depends, in part, upon the separation of the concepts of state and society in the Western political imagination. Neither of these assumptions is uncontentious. While there clearly does exist a plethora of groups, communities, and associations in relative separation from the state, the boundary between state and civil society in many countries is rarely as clear or firm as the first assumption suggests. In various democracies, the state and other public authorities succeeded in incorporating institutions and organizations from civil society—for instance, trade unions, environmental groups, and business associations—into key networks of influence and decision making. Equally, individual groups and even oppositional social movements often expend considerable resources and energy attempting to interact with government officials, elected politicians, and state bureaucracies. The notion that the state–civil society distinction exists in all Western societies therefore requires considerable clarification and qualification in empirical terms.
Likewise, the idea that a fundamental intellectual distinction between state and society underpins the model of liberal democracy begs some rather large questions. Quite different accounts of the distinction and interrelationship between society and the state guided some of the major ideologies of the 19th and 20th centuries and sustained clashing theories about politics, sovereignty, and social order. Above all, the idea that a portion of any societal complex should be portioned off, endowed with ethical, even emancipatory, significance, and understood as the fundamental opponent of political authority and institutional life looks increasingly problematic in the early 21st century.
One of the most interesting and contentious manifestations of the terminology of civil society arises from its increasingly common application to non-Western societies. Are supporters of civil society in the West and in newly democratizing states throughout the world talking about the same things when they invoke this term? Can a Western-derived term be usefully employed as a framework for analyzing societies with forms of sociability and state-society relationships that differ markedly from those of the West? Equally, the assumption of some Anglo-American theory that a network of independent associations, cultural practices, and organizations is a necessary feature of a stable democracy is open to considerable doubt when viewed from elsewhere in the world (think, for instance, of East Asian countries that have many of the features of civil societies but are not democratic in their political structures).
During the 1990s, in particular, many authors, politicians, and public authorities keen to find solutions to some of the different kinds of problems facing developing countries seized upon civil society as a kind of panacea. Relatedly, this term became a conceptual mainstay of academic thinking about democratic transitions and a familiar part of the discourse of global institutions, leading nongovernmental organizations, and Western governments. The ideological character and political implications of such ideas have become increasingly clear over time. Such thinking helped sustain various attempts to kick-start civil societies from “above” in different African countries, for example, and simultaneously served to legitimize Western ideas about the kinds of political structure and economic order appropriate for developing states. In philosophical terms, applying civil society in this kind of way raises the profound question of whether it can be removed from its status within the Western political imagination and applied in ways that are appropriate for the indigenous developmental trajectories and political cultures of some of the poorest countries in the world.
It is impossible to divest the notion of civil society of normative connotations. The concept remains powerful, in part, because of its (often unstated) contrastive character. A civil society is typically seen as a superior alternative to a barbarian, natural, despotic, traditional, or premodern societal “other.” This kind of idea constitutes an inexorable part of the term’s appeal within the Western political imagination. The achievement of a dense forest of groups, networks, and organizations that appears to stand beyond the boundaries of the state and outside the reach of the family and clan remains, for many political thinkers, a major part of what makes Western modernity unique and desirable. When examined closely, this generic idea gives way to a host of different kinds of projects, fantasies, and anxieties about politics, society, and the economy.
Since the 1990s, civil society has moved to the centre stage of Western political debate, assuming the character of both the diagnosis for and the solution to the various malaises of Western society—rampant individualism, rising crime, consumerism, and the decline of community, among other maladies. In more philosophical terms, it has held out two different kinds of promise to intellectuals, political actors, and, occasionally, social movements. On one hand, it offers the dream of reconciling some of the major discursive tensions in Western thought—between, for instance, self-interest and the public good, the individual and the community, freedom and social solidarity, and the private and public domains of life. And the second promise, the idea of civil society as a distinct third sector of Western societies (distinct from both the state and the private realm), has come to fire parts of the radical imagination in contemporary ideological debate. In this context it offers the thinly veiled promise of the achievement of a collective emancipation from the constraints, compromises, and disappointments of politics. With a growing awareness of the limitations and dangers of both of these ideas has come a desire to rethink the boundaries of civil society and reconsider which political and moral values it promotes.
Michael Kenny