Social and historical projections of existentialism
- Related Topics:
- Dasein
- dread
- authentic existence
- theological existentialism
- absurdity
The metaphysical or theological dimension of existentialism does not leave humans with nothing to do. Once the nullity of the existential possibilities is recognized, humans cannot but resign themselves to Being, which, in one of its new manifestations in the world or beyond it, conducts them to a new epoch. Even someone like José Ortega y Gasset, the Spanish existentialist and writer, who, in examining the social aspects of existence, characterized his epoch by the advent of the masses and the socialization of humans, halted at the recognition of the crisis and the total uncertainty that dominates the future of humanity (La rebelión de las masas [1929; The Revolt of the Masses).
On the other hand, humanistic existentialism recognized the positive and the to-some-degree determining function that humans may have in history. It insisted, as in Merleau-Ponty, on the individual’s duty to assume the responsibility of an effective action for the transformation of society and, in general, of the world that he inhabits.
Along that line of assuming responsibility, existentialism moved toward Marxism, with which it shares the diagnoses of existence as the primordial and ineradicable relationship of humans with nature and with society. In the Critique de la raison dialectique (1960; Critique of Dialectical Reason), Sartre attempted a synthesis between existentialism and Marxism by modifying the notion of “project” that he defended in Being and Nothingness and by utilizing the notion of dialectic as understood by Marx. The project of which existence consists is not the result of an arbitrary choice (as Sartre had previously maintained); it is, instead, that of a conditioning by the objective possibilities that Sartre identifies (as does Marx) with “the material conditions of existence.” The project remains, however, that of the particular individual of a unique consciousness—but of a consciousness that tries to become totalized, or to enter into relationship with others so as to constitute, with others, human groups that are more and more comprehensive. In that manner it tends toward a complete and definitive totalization without appeals. Dialectical reason would be precisely such a process of growing totalization; and it becomes, moreover, the true protagonist of history and becomes that with which the interior freedom of any individuals who participate in history is identified.
From the defense of the freedom of the individual, Sartre thus moved to the defense of the absolute dialectical necessity of history despite its being interiorized and lived by individuals. A historical project of human life that tries to remove the characteristics of inauthenticity or of alienation from existence—a project that may bring existentialism and Marxism close together—thus ends by losing, in that form, its risky and problematic character and the awareness of the conditions and the modalities of its realization. Those features are also lost in the “transcendental project” of a new society elaborated by one of the leaders of the New Left, the German-born American philosopher Herbert Marcuse. While insisting on the requirement that the “transcendental project” be “in accord with the real possibilities open at the attained level of the material and intellectual culture,” Marcuse entrusted its realization to an impersonal and contemplative Reason, which cannot but invite the “great refusal” of contemporary society.
Having developed in different and contrasting directions, existentialism has furnished philosophy and the whole of contemporary culture with conceptual tools, of which the nature and techniques of employment have still not been clarified—as, for example, terms like “problematicity,” “chance,” “condition,” “choice,” “freedom,” and “project.” Although such tools can be employed usefully for the interpretation of existence—i.e., to orient philosophical inquiry in the fields of epistemology, ethics, aesthetics, education, and politics—it is nonetheless indispensable that the pivot on which they turn, “possibility,” be granted its own ontological status that does not reduce it either to Nothingness or to Being. It is indispensable, moreover, that a positive datum be perceived in possibility, a datum that is verifiable with appropriate techniques and that, while not offering infallible guarantees, allows one to project and to act in the world with calculated risks and with a prudent trust.