- Key People:
- Publius Nigidius Figulus
In geometry, the Pythagoreans cannot be credited with any proofs in the Euclidean sense. They were evidently concerned, however, with some speculation on geometrical figures, as in the case of the Pythagorean theorem, and the concept that the point, line, triangle, and tetrahedron correspond to the elements of the tetraktys, since they are determined by one, two, three, and four points, respectively. They possibly knew practical methods of constructing the five regular solids, but the theoretical basis for such constructions was given by non-Pythagoreans in the 4th century.
It is notable that the properties of the circle seem not to have interested the early Pythagoreans. But perhaps the tradition that Pythagoras himself discovered that the sum of the three angles of any triangle is equal to two right angles may be trusted. The idea of geometric proportions is probably Pythagorean in origin; but the so-called golden section—which divides a line at a point such that the smaller part is to the greater as the greater is to the whole—is hardly an early Pythagorean contribution (see golden ratio). Some advance in geometry was made at a later date, by 4th-century Pythagoreans; e.g., Archytas offered an interesting solution to the problem of the duplication of the cube—in which a cube twice the volume of a given cube is constructed—by an essentially geometrical construction in three dimensions; and the conception of geometry as a “flow” of points into lines, of lines into surfaces, and so on, may have been contributed by Archytas; but on the whole the numerous achievements of non-Pythagorean mathematicians were in fact more conspicuous than those of the Pythagoreans.
Music
The achievements of the early Pythagoreans in musical theory are somewhat less controversial. The scientific approach to music, in which musical intervals are expressed as numerical proportions, originated with them, as did also the more specific idea of harmonic “means.” At an early date they discovered empirically that the basic intervals of Greek music include the elements of the tetraktys, since they have the proportions 1:2 (octave), 3:2 (fifth), and 4:3 (fourth). The discovery could have been made, for instance, in pipes or flutes or stringed instruments: the tone of a plucked string held at its middle is an octave higher than that of the whole string; the tone of a string held at the 2/3 point is a fifth higher; and that of one held at the 3/4 point is a fourth higher. Moreover, they noticed that the subtraction of intervals is accomplished by dividing these ratios by one another. In the course of the 5th century they calculated the intervals for the usual diatonic scale, the tone being represented by 9:8 (fifth minus fourth); i.e., 3/2 ÷ 4/3, and the semitone by 256:243 (fourth minus two tones); i.e., 4/3 ÷ (9/8 × 9/8). Archytas made some modification to this doctrine and also worked out the relationships of the notes in the chromatic (12-tone) scale and the enharmonic scale (involving such minute differences as that between A flat and G sharp, which on a piano are played by the same key).
Astronomy
In their cosmological views the earliest Pythagoreans probably differed little from their Ionian predecessors. They made a point of studying the stellar heavens; but—with the possible exception of the theory of musical intervals in the cosmos—no new contributions to astronomy can be ascribed to them with any degree of probability. Late in the 5th century, or possibly in the 4th century, a Pythagorean boldly abandoned the geocentric view and posited a cosmological model in which the Earth, Sun, and stars circle about an (unseen) central fire—a view traditionally attributed to the 5th-century Pythagorean Philolaus of Croton.
History of Pythagoreanism
The life of Pythagoras and the origins of Pythagoreanism appear only dimly through a thick veil of legend and semihistorical tradition. The literary sources for the teachings of the Pythagoreans present extremely complicated problems. Special difficulties arise from the oral and esoteric transmission of the early doctrines, the profuse accumulation of tendentious legends, and the considerable amount of confusion that was caused by the split in the school in the 5th century bce. In the 4th century, Plato’s inclination toward Pythagoreanism created a tendency—manifest already in the middle of the century in the works of his pupils—to interpret Platonic concepts as originally Pythagorean. But the radical skepticism as to the reliability of the sources shown by some scholars has on the whole been abandoned. It now seems possible to extract bits of reliable evidence from a wide range of ancient authors, such as Porphyry and Iamblichus (see below Neo-Pythagoreanism).
Most of these literary sources hark back ultimately to the environment of Plato and Aristotle; and here the importance of one of Aristotle’s students has become obvious, viz., the musicologist and philosopher Aristoxenus, who in spite of his bias possessed firsthand information independent of the point of view of Plato’s Academy. The role played by Dicaearchus, another of Aristotle’s pupils, and by the Sicilian historian Timaeus, of the early 3rd century bce, is less clear. The reliability of Aristotle’s account of Pythagoreanism has also been emphasized against the doubts that had been expressed by some scholars; but Aristotle’s sources, in turn, hardly lead farther back than to the late 5th century (perhaps to Philolaus; see below Two Pythagorean sects). In addition, there are scattered hints in various early authors and in some not very substantial remains of 4th-century Pythagorean literature. The mosaic of reconstruction thus has to be to some extent subjective.