Table of Contents
References & Edit History Related Topics
print Print
Please select which sections you would like to print:
verifiedCite
While every effort has been made to follow citation style rules, there may be some discrepancies. Please refer to the appropriate style manual or other sources if you have any questions.
Select Citation Style
Feedback
Corrections? Updates? Omissions? Let us know if you have suggestions to improve this article (requires login).
Thank you for your feedback

Our editors will review what you’ve submitted and determine whether to revise the article.

The period after the death of Aristotle was characterized by the decay of the Greek city-states, which then became pawns in the power game of the Hellenistic kings who succeeded Alexander. Life became troubled and insecure. It was in this environment that two dogmatic philosophical systems came into being, Stoicism and Epicureanism, which promised to give their adherents something to hold onto and to make them independent of the external world.

Stoicism

The Stoic system was created by Zeno of Citium (c. 335–c. 263 bce), who went to Athens as a merchant. He stayed at Athens, heard the lectures of various philosophers, and—after he had elaborated his own philosophy—began to teach in a public hall, the Stoa Poikile (hence the name Stoicism).

Zeno’s thought comprised, essentially, a dogmatized Socratic philosophy, with added ingredients derived from Heracleitus (c. 540–c. 480 bce). The basis of human happiness, he said, is to live “in agreement” with oneself, a statement that was later replaced by the formula “to live in agreement with nature.” The only real good for a human being is the possession of virtue; everything else—wealth or poverty, health or illness, life or death—is completely indifferent. All virtues are based exclusively on right knowledge, self-control (sōphrosynē) being the knowledge of the right choice, fortitude the knowledge of what must be endured and what must not, and justice the right knowledge “in distribution.” The passions, which are the cause of all evil, are the result of error in judging what is a real good and what is not. Because it is difficult to see, however, why murder, fraud, and theft should be considered evil if life and possessions are of no value, the doctrine was later modified to distinguish between “preferable things,” such as having the necessities of life and health, “completely indifferent things,” and “anti-preferable things,” such as lacking the necessities of life or health—while insisting still that the happiness of the truly wise person could not be impaired by illness, pain, hunger, or any deprivation of external goods. In the beginning, Zeno also insisted that an individual is either completely wise, in which case he would never do anything wrong and would be completely happy, or he is a fool. Later he made the concession, however, that there are people who are not completely wise but who are progressing toward wisdom. Although these people might even have true insight, they are not certain that they have it, whereas the truly wise person is also certain of having true insight. The world is governed by divine logos—a word originally meaning “word” or “speech,” then (with Heracleitus) a speech that expresses the laws of the universe, then (finally) “reason.” This logos keeps the world in perfect order. Human beings can deviate from or rebel against this order, but, by doing so, they cannot disturb it but can only do harm to themselves.

Zeno’s philosophy was further developed by Cleanthes (c. 331–c. 232 bce), the second head of the school, and by Chrysippus (c. 280–c. 206 bce), its third head. Chrysippus elaborated a new kind of logic, which did not receive much attention outside the Stoic school until recent times; this “propositional logic” has been hailed by some logicians as superior to the “conceptual logic” of Aristotle. Panaetius of Rhodes (c. 180–109 bce) adapted Stoic philosophy to the needs of the Roman aristocracy, whose members then governed the Western world, and made a great impression on some of the leading figures of the time, who tried to follow his moral precepts. In the following century, a time of civil war, slave rebellions, and the decay of the Roman Republic, Poseidonius of Apamea (c. 135–c. 51 bce), who was also one of the most brilliant historians of all times, taught that the Stoic takes a position above the rest of humankind, looking down on its struggles as on a spectacle. In the period of the consolidation of the empire, Stoicism became the religion of the republican opposition. The most famous Stoic was the younger Cato (95–46 bce), who committed suicide after the victory of Julius Caesar (c. 100–44 bce). It was also the guiding philosophy of Seneca the Younger (c. 4 bce–65 ce), the educator and (for a long time) the adviser of the emperor Nero (37–68), who tried to keep Nero on the path of virtue but failed and finally was forced to commit suicide on Nero’s orders. Despite the oddities of Zeno’s original doctrine, Stoicism gave consolation, composure, and fortitude in times of trouble to many proud individuals to the end of antiquity and beyond.