Computable probability spaces

print Print
Please select which sections you would like to print:
verifiedCite
While every effort has been made to follow citation style rules, there may be some discrepancies. Please refer to the appropriate style manual or other sources if you have any questions.
Select Citation Style
Feedback
Corrections? Updates? Omissions? Let us know if you have suggestions to improve this article (requires login).
Thank you for your feedback

Our editors will review what you’ve submitted and determine whether to revise the article.

Finally, it is to be observed that the concept of chance or random number, wherever it has occurred in the above discussion, submits to the interpretation of result of observation of an experiment or physical phenomenon. The chance ingredients in the weather data to which prediction theory applies could be due to molecular disturbances in the atmosphere that are of diverse and minute origin. The chance failure that might cause a component breakdown in a computing machine is due to the physical structure and environment of the defaulting part. The source of chance that could be used to augment the input of a computer for the purposes of the Monte-Carlo method of calculation may be chosen as the erratic emission of electrons from the cathode of an electronic tube and is frequently so chosen.

An entirely distinct question is involved in relating chance and computers. It would be important to know whether an automaton in the sense defined by Turing can generate random numbers. The question is tantamount to asking whether a Turing machine can logically describe the behaviour of those sources of chance that are found in nature and are the subject of the study of probability theory. Because there are many points of view—too many to consider here—more tightly phrased questions may serve as an introduction to the subject, and a few conclusions that can be brought as answers will be mentioned. At the outset, one limited question can be affirmatively answered: Can a computable sequence of numbers, S = (a1, a2, a3, · · · ), serve as the basic ingredient of a probability theory by providing all of the necessary points in a probability space? In this question the term computable sequence is defined to mean that the numbers ak are real and there is a Turing machine that, for any pair of positive integers A, B, will print out in order the first A digits of all ak, for k ranging from 1 to B, in a finite number of steps. It might appear that an affirmative answer to the above question is not striking if simple probability theory alone is considered—that is, a theory of events in which the number of possible outcomes is finite, as in the theory of dice, coins, roulette, and the like. On the other hand, it was shown in 1960 that, although a computable sequence can serve as a set of points in a simple probability space, the mathematical expectations of all random variables X defined on the space can be computed according to an explicit algorithm (see 6) that makes use of the sample values, X(a1), X (a2), X(a3), · · ·, which themselves are computable if X is computable. In this algorithm it is evident that the potential number of values to be calculated is infinite, though the number of possible outcomes (distinct values of X) might be finite.

In the language of the limited question considered, a listing of all sample values (random numbers) of an infinite sequence of statistically independent random variables can be printed out by a Turing machine, at least in the simple case, with strict adherence to the definition of all probabilistic terms as based on measure theory, the theory that generalizes the concept of length.

Extension of such constructions beyond the simple case has also been shown to be possible, provided the concept of a random variable can be extended to a class of functions that are more general than the measure-theoretic class. The most explicit formulation of a suitable generalization was given in 1966, and on the basis of this work it is possible to answer affirmatively a second question: For any sequence of probability distributions, is there a sequence of statistically independent random variables with these respective distributions, each of whose sample values can be computed on a Turing machine and whose mathematical expectations are also attainable by algorithm?

Such results would seem to affront the intuition that tends to divide phenomena into deterministic (or computable) and random (or uncomputable) parts. It is to be observed, however, that in probabilistic matters, passage to the limit and infinite collections are essential ingredients, and such entities are unfamiliar objects in the world in which intuitions are formed.

Bayard Rankin