Medieval Platonism
With the gradual revival of philosophical thinking in the West that began in the Carolingian period (late 8th–9th centuries), the history of Platonism becomes extremely complex. Only a sketch distinguishing the main streams of a more or less Platonic tradition is given here.
In the 4th century the Christian exegete Calcidius (Chalcidius) prepared a commentary on Plato’s Timaeus, which exerted an important influence on its medieval interpretation. A Christian Platonic theism of the type of which Boethius is the finest example thus arose; based on a reading of the Timaeus with Christian eyes, it continued to have a strong influence in the Middle Ages, especially in the earlier period. This kind of theism, issuing in a strongly positive view of God’s creation and a nobly austere but humane view of human duty and destiny, was particularly apparent in the Christian humanism of the School of Chartres (12th century).
The widest, deepest, and most persistent Christian Platonist influence in the Latin West was that of Augustine (see above Augustinian Platonism). Augustinianism in a variety of forms—often stiffened, exaggerated, or distorted—persisted throughout the Middle Ages and survived the “recovery of Aristotle.” In the later Middle Ages Augustine’s influence was particularly strong in the Franciscan school, though not confined to it. But the greatest and most influential of medieval thinkers deeply influenced by Augustine was Anselm of Canterbury (1033/34–1109), the originator (probably on the basis of suggestions in Augustine) of the still much discussed “ontological argument” for the existence of God (see religion, philosophy of) and a philosopher whose humility, openness, and readiness to consider objections had a genuinely Socratic quality.
One of the boldest and most original thinkers of medieval Europe was John Scotus Erigena (810–c. 877), who introduced to the West the Greek Christian Platonist tradition (see above Patristic Platonism), as it had been developed by Gregory of Nyssa, the Pseudo-Dionysius, and Maximus the Confessor. His views were much disapproved of by the Western church; and his great philosophical work, the Periphyseon (usually known as De divisione naturae [On the Division of Nature]), was not much read and ceased to be copied after his condemnation in 1210. But a considerable part of the text circulated in the form of anonymous glosses to the Latin translations of the Pseudo-Dionysius (of which the first adequate translation was by Erigena himself); and in this way his thought influenced both the tradition of Western mysticism, which derived from the Pseudo-Dionysius, and 13th-century Scholasticism, for which St. Paul’s supposed disciple was still a major authority.
There is no more superficial and misleading generalization in the history of philosophy than that which sharply opposes “Christian Platonism” and “Christian Aristotelianism.” To be sure, the recovery of the authentic thought of Aristotle through Latin translations of his works in the 12th and 13th centuries was indeed a major event in the history of philosophy. But Platonism and Aristotelianism have never been tidily separated in the history of European thought. There was already a strong Aristotelian element in Middle Platonism and Neoplatonism. Byzantine theologians (in the East) from the 6th century ce onward were as Aristotelian as anybody in western Europe in the 13th century. Thirteenth-century “Aristotelian” Scholastics, though much preoccupied with the new translations of Aristotle and their philosophical and theological implications, were still deeply influenced by Augustine, Boethius, and the Pseudo-Dionysius (with glosses derived from Erigena). And the Islamic philosophy, to be mentioned below, with which they had to grapple, was as much Neoplatonist as it was Aristotelian. Further, they also were influenced by Latin translations of two pseudo-Aristotelian works in Arabic, based on Neoplatonic sources, as well as by those of some of the shorter works of Proclus (see above The later Neoplatonists). It has been said that “Aquinas is closer to Plotinus than to the real Aristotle,” and there is some truth in this judgment.
Islamic and medieval Jewish philosophy
After the Muslim conquest of Syria and Egypt, there began a great work of translation of the texts that had been studied in the late Greek philosophical schools—including a number of dialogues of Plato and Neoplatonic treatises, as well as the works of Aristotle and a number of the Alexandrian Neoplatonist commentaries on them. The translations—partly from Greek, partly from Syriac versions of the Greek texts—were made between about 800 and 1000. On the basis of these translated texts an impressive development of Islamic theology and philosophy took place, strongly influenced by Neoplatonism, though Aristotelian influence also became increasingly important. An interesting feature of this Islamic philosophy, which distinguished it from the familiar Neoplatonism, was the reappearance of an interest in the political and social side of Plato’s thought. The tradition may be seen in four great Muslim philosophers, the Arab al-Kindī (c. 800–870), the Turk al-Fārābī (c. 878–c. 950), and two who deeply influenced the medieval West, Avicenna (Ibn Sīnā, 980–1037) from Persia and Averroës (Ibn Rushd, 1126–98) from Muslim Spain. Of these, Avicenna was perhaps the more Platonist, and Averroës, whose fame and influence rested primarily on his commentaries on Aristotle, was the more Aristotelian, although the latter’s commentaries were written on the basis of Greek ones, some of whose authors had used them as a vehicle for Neoplatonism.
Medieval Jewish philosophy, which also developed within this Muslim intellectual tradition, reflected—at least in its earlier phases—strong Neoplatonic influence. This is especially true of the thought of the early figure Isaac Israeli (mid-9th to mid-10th century), whose Platonism was pervasive, though derivative and less than fully coherent, and the first great Jewish philosopher of Muslim Spain, Avicebron (Ibn Gabirol, c. 1022–c. 1058/70), whose Platonism may have been derived from Israeli’s. Avicebron’s Fons vitae (Fountain of Life) was also a major influence on Scholastic philosophers.